Arielista Elitism and Geopolitical Exigencies
in Post-War Colombia, 1902-1910 

Shawn McDaniel
The Graduate Center and Lehman College, CUNY

 Colombian history of the early twentieth century is rife with a number of serious geopolitical challenges.  Exclusionary politics caused a series of civil wars, which in turn frustrated international trade and provoked a severe economic recession.  Moreover, those conflicts facilitated U.S. intervention into Colombian affairs, which resulted in the secession of Panama in 1903 and gave the United States proprietary rights of the construction of the Panama Canal.  In the wake of these national catastrophes, Colombian writer and statesman Carlos Arturo Torres (1867-1911) published an essay entitled êdola fori (1910) in which he advocated a national reconciliation that moves beyond hyper-partisanship and embraces wider democratic participation.  In his prologue to êdola fori, however, Uruguayan essayist JosŽ Enrique Rod— criticized TorresÕs anti-elitist conceptions.  In this article, I will underscore the limitations of Rod—Õs elitist insistence by exploring the geopolitical exigencies in post-war Colombia that inform TorresÕs êdola fori.
Torres was an active essayist, poet, and journalist. (1) Even though êdola fori concentrates on political superstitions in Latin America, TorresÕs affinity for British thought is clear.  Torres spent nearly a decade in England, writing êdola fori while living in Liverpool as a consul of the Colombian government.  He published a well-known book entitled Estudios ingleses (1906) in which he commented on, among other topics, Shakespeare, Byron, and Spencer (Salazar C‡ceres 65).  Moreover, êdola fori borrows its title from one of the four idols that English philosopher Francis Bacon criticizes in his Novum Organum (1620), the idols of the Marketplace. (2)
Although largely dismissed today, êdola fori is one of the most valuable documents of its time about the history of ideas in Latin America. Critics have read êdola fori in contradictory ways.  Although many critics extend it a brief, approbatory nod, the shadow of Ariel has essentially obscured its importance in the contemporary canon. Although we may think that this omission is due to the non-literary nature of êdola fori, as TorresÕs essay is expositional, even revered critical opinions of the essay in Latin America that do take a closer look at it downplay its importance.  For instance, Medardo Vitier, an influential Cuban critic on Latin American intellectual history, criticizes êdola fori for its excessive references to European ideas (157). In addition, in a seminal study on the Latin American essay, Historia del ensayo hispanoamericano (1973), U.S. academics Peter Earle and Robert Mead suggest that Torres is intolerant. (3) By contrast, a more recent reading by Colombian scholar RubŽn Sierra Mej’a regards êdola fori a nonpolemical, serene text that demonstrates a clear concern for bipartisanship and national reconciliation in the wake of serious challenges to ColombiaÕs sovereignty (ÒEl intelectualÓ 212). Although critics disagree about the tone of TorresÕs essay, they generally accept that Torres was one of the clearest proponents of arielismo in Latin America (Altamirano 10; DevŽs ValdŽs 26).
Although they never met in person, Rod— and Torres praised each otherÕs work in personal correspondence and literary articles. When Torres published êdola fori (4) in 1910, Rod— wrote an enthusiastic article supporting it entitled ÒRumbos nuevos.Ó Although in this article Rod— celebrates TorresÕs message of tolerance, as well as other standard arielista facets of the essay, Rod— affords relatively little space to a direct analysis of êdola fori. Instead, Rod— uses TorresÕs essay as a pretext to explicate, as he had done in Ariel, the neospiritualist movement in Latin America that seeks to supersede the confines of positivism.
In ÒRumbos nuevosÓ Rod— enumerates various criticisms against positivism. However, Rod— also underscores positivismÕs favorable contributions to Latin American thought. For Rod—, a pure European positivism was not transplanted to Latin America; rather, a corrupted form concerned solely with utilitarian empiricism and material wealth surfaced. Rod— claims that by omitting higher ideals, positivism codified a contradictory emulation in the masses: Òcreyendo predicar la filosof’a que hab’an aprendido, predicaban la imitaci—n de su propia naturalezaÓ (43). To put it another way, positivism insisted that only science can reveal the real world.  Those who accept the validity of this doctrine believe they are discovering the world the way it really is, which subsequently devalues any components outside the scientific realm.
While Rod—Õs criticisms of positivism mirror those he offers in Ariel, he specifies its invaluable contributions to intellectual life in the twentieth century:

La iniciaci—n positivista dej— en nosotros, para lo especulativo como para lo de la pr‡ctica y la acci—n, su potente sentido de relatividad; la justa consideraci—n de las realidades terrenas; la vigilancia e insistencia del esp’ritu cr’tico; la desconfianza para las afirmaciones absolutas; el respeto de las condiciones de tiempo y de lugar; la cuidadosa adaptaci—n de los medios a los fines; el reconocimiento del valor y del hecho m’nimo y del esfuerzo lento y paciente en cualquier gŽnero de obra; el desdŽn de la intenci—n ilusa, del arrebato estŽril, de la vana anticipaci—n. RumbosÓ 46)

 Rod—, however, sought to mobilize a young generation of Latin Americans to seek higher spiritual ideals outside the realm of positivism. For that reason, Rod— clarifies that this kind of idealism differs from its spiritualist and romantic predecessors in that it is informed by positivism, but not restricted by it. Rod— summarizes this evolution in the following way: ÒEl positivismo, que es la piedra angular de nuestra formaci—n intelectual, no es ya la cœpula que la remata y coronaÓ (ÒRumbosÓ 45). For Rod— and other ÒarielistasÓ like Francisco Garc’a Calder—n, who wrote a prologue to the second edition of êdola fori published in Madrid in 1916, Torres and his essay are indicative of this idealistic trend that steers positivism towards higher ideals.
On
the opening page of êdola fori, Torres identifies the prevalence of uncritical ideas as a threat to Latin American societies: ÒBien es sabido que Bacon llama Òêdolos del ForoÓ (Idola Fori) aquellas f—rmulas o ideas "verdaderas supersticiones pol’ticas" que continœan imperando en el esp’ritu despuŽs de que una cr’tica racional ha demostrado su falsedadÓ (17). êdola fori applies BaconÕs critical lense to Latin American democracies in order to denounce traps in thinking and understanding due to Òcriterios falsos producidos por el empleo inconsciente de tŽrminos que se imponen, cargados de un sentido ilusorioÓ (Vitier 162-163). (5) This disconnect between the words used to indicate ideas and the actual relationship between these two elements is responsible for the persistence of political idols in Latin America because people all too readily lend their support to a leader or party without fully understanding the specifics of their political platforms. Far from ArielÕs highly literary construction of an idealized classroom, êdola fori is a sociopolitical treatise written during an era of hyper-partisanship, violence, and economic decline, which is a state of crisis that has defined Colombian politics to this day.
In the second half of the nineteenth century, in addition to fifty nine local revolts, there were six civil wars in Colombia: 1860, 1875, 1876, 1885, 1895, and the guerra de los Mil D’as (1899-1902) (Posada Carb— 62). The twentieth century dawned in the midst of an endless stream of national conflicts. The civil war commonly known as los Mil D’as erupted in large part because of political and economic disparities between Conservatives, who favored a centralized, religious state, and Liberals, who preferred stronger regional governments and a separation of church and state. Between 1878 and 1898, the Conservative PartyÕs regeneracionista program instituted an extreme centralism that gave the conservative head of state virtually unchallenged authority to appoint local and national officials, with Liberals largely excluded from government. For example, between 1888 and 1904 no liberals were appointed to the Senate (Fischer 77).  President Rafael Nœ–ez codified the regenerationist vision in a new Constitution in 1886, a document drafted by his predecessor, Miguel Antonio Caro, who in turn continued this policy until los Mil D’as. The Constitution of 1886 was at odds with liberalism in that it sanctioned and institutionalized the power of the Catholic Church in national matters such as education and censure of dissidence, which is to say anyone who expressed anti-governmental, anti-religious, and ÒimmoralÓ sentiments in newspapers. However, the exclusivity of conservative political appointments relegated many liberal elite to industry and trade, and some got very rich in the international coffee market. By the mid-1890s, however, participating in the international market required monetary modernization, including adopting the gold standard. The conservative government, however, resisted and defended traditional agriculture and monetary policy, which stifled imports and exports (Fischer 77). Frustrated, many liberals took up arms to overthrow the government.
It goes without saying that Los Mil D’as was devastating for Colombia. Approximately 100,000 people died in the guerrilla warfare that spanned much of the Colombian geography (Fischer 81). (6) The war ravaged ColombiaÕs economy and plunged the country into a recession that lasted until 1910 (Fischer 40). In addition to the devaluation of the national currency on international markets, there was widespread robbery and corruption (Fischer 80). By 1902, the year in which a peace treaty was signed by conservative and liberal leaders on board the U.S. battleship Wisconsin, it was generally acknowledged that the costs of the conflict outweighed its possible benefits. In addition to the discernible political, economic, and civil catastrophes, many were concerned that the war had jeopardized the very national sovereignty the Regeneraci—n had endeavored so diligently to construct (S‡nchez and Aguilera 24).
As the latter stages of the conflict became concentrated in the Colombian isthmus of Panama, a liberal stronghold, the United States intervened citing article 35 of the Mallarino-Bidlack Treaty of 1846, which permitted the United States to ensure free transit (Fischer 92). Of course, President Theodore Roosevelt realized the strategic importance for the United States in the Panama Canal, which by that point was well under construction by a French company. In fact, ownership of the Canal was one of the most important facets of the peace accord (Fischer 94).  With the support of the United States, Panama seceded from Colombia one year later. Soon after in 1904, the United States purchased the Canal and the U.S. Army Corps of Engineers oversaw its construction until its completion in 1914.
Recognition by the United States of the internal ideological and political divide in Colombia, not to mention the CanalÕs strategic importance, no doubt led to U.S. intervention into sovereign Colombian territory. While this was widely recognized, many Colombians understandably viewed the geo-psychological severing of their nation by the United States as a calculated, imperialist maneuver. It is little wonder that many Colombians subsequently embraced the North/South paradigm of arielismo, which posed Latin American nations as culturally distinct from the United States and its materialist drives, as a national narrative (Fischer 96). 
This historical context is essential when reading êdola fori because in it Torres criticizes the political extremisms responsible for this national decline.  In addition, TorresÕs essay is emblematic of a conscious post-war political and civil reconciliation. This was a platform forwarded by conservative President Rafael Reyes (1904-1909) that resulted in constitutional reforms in 1904 and 1905 that curbed the extreme centralism implemented by the Regeneration (S‡nchez and Aguilera 23). Torres, as he had previously done at the height of political fanaticism at the outset of los Mil D’as, participated once again in a conservative government as a Colombian consul in Liverpool.
In the wake of this geopolitical catastrophe, Torres seeks to correct the Òherd instinctÓ that he insists precludes many Latin Americans from discerning the flaws in the political dogmas they so ardently defend. Torres challenges this cognitive dissonance by proposing a serene, critical independence based on the Spencerian notions of relativity and evolution, which he examines from a historicist perspective: ÒLa marcha del pensamiento humano en veinte a–os ha demostrado hasta donde pueden complementarse, ampliarse y rectificarse conclusiones que parec’an definitivas y hasta d—nde alcanza, segœn la gr‡fica expresi—n del mismo Spencer, a evolucionar el sistema de evoluci—nÓ (22). Certainty and fixed criteria, then, are illusory and Torres underscores this idea by highlighting the discrepant interpretations that the same event or historical figure receive in different time periods: Òquien pretenda descubrir al travŽs de los anales humanos y a la luz de un juicio predeterminado el hilo continuo de un principio dado en sus desarrollos hist—ricos,Ése ver’a extraviado en un dŽdalo de imposible orientaci—nÓ (91-92).    A principal objective in êdola fori centers on subverting the idea of dogmatic certainty that incites violence and tyranny: Òhay el fanatismo de la religi—n y el fanatismo de la irreligi—n; la superstici—n de la fe y la superstici—n de la raz—n; la idolatr’a de la tradici—n y la idolatr’a de la ciencia; la intransigencia de lo antiguo y la intransigencia de lo nuevo; el despotismo teol—gico y el despotismo nacionalista; la incomprensi—n conservadora y la incomprensi—n liberalÓ (26).  Torres argues that fanaticisms are illogical and detrimental because every facet of existence is subject to change. Although he admired Spencer, Torres laments that the predominant Òthought shapersÓ of the modern epoch, which is to say the evolutionary theories of Darwin and Spencer, have become strict dogmas in virtually all areas of existence and knowledge: ÒLa moral, la pol’tica y la sociolog’a buscaban all’ sus orientaciones definitivas; la historia, la literatura y la estŽtica se modelaban sobre aquellas nociones que, verificadas en un orden, exclusivo de hechos cient’ficos, el de la anatom’a, aparec’an como el fin de todos los fen—menos vitales en todos los dominios del conocimientoÓ (67). Torres challenges these scientific dogmatisms by arguing that scientific truths, far from being static, incessantly fluctuate.  He cites two contemporary thinkers whose ideas have modified or expanded evolutionary theories: French biologist and naturalist RenŽ Quinton (1866-1925) and French philosopher Henri Bergson (1859-1941).
In 1896, Quinton, commonly referred to as Òthe French Darwin,Ó proposes a theory of constance that holds that life is not, as Darwin contends, uncontrolled and unlimited transformation.  Rather, Quinton asserts that an Òoriginal conditionÓ is maintained in each organism throughout time (Torres 69). The importance of QuintonÕs theory of constance, as well as his subsequent arguments outlined in LÕEau de mer, milieu organique (1904), resides in his view that life determines nature, which challenges the deterministic underpinnings of DarwinÕs theory of evolution.  In a similar transformative effort, Bergson tried to re-establish the link between the physical and the metaphysical that positivism negated by proposing a new type of evolution in his L'Evolution crŽatrice (1907). BergsonÕs creative evolution denies all determinisms by reclaiming intuition, spontaneity, and idealism.  BergsonÕs ideas quickly became prevalent in Latin America and were particularly influential during the neospiritual wave that swept Latin America in the first two decades of the twentieth century (Guy 121).
Torres highlights the ways in which Quinton and Bergson rework the theory of evolution in order to signal the alterability of science as well as relativize the idea of certainty. For Torres, modernity necessitates dynamic rather than static ways of thinking, and he maintains that progress should be measured not by the quantity of certainties but by the number of conceptions that are open to or have experienced modification (Torres 27). The danger of convictions, Torres claims, is that they halt action and devalue accuracy. This is why Torres proposes a critical independence unrestrained by science and mysticism as a viable method for harmony and progress: ÒEl mostrar lo caduco de lo que se tiene generalmente por definitivo y la falibilidad de lo que se tiene generalmente por dogm‡tico, es llegar, no a la liberaci—n del pensamiento y a la plenitud de la vida, porque Žsta es una meta inaccesible, pero a lo menos a las sendas de ascensi—n que a ella conducenÓ (74). This critical independence should not, however, translate into conviction; rather, it should accept the inexistence of coherent narratives and embrace constant modification. Torres calls the freedom to think critically and independently Òthe rotation of ideas,Ó which oscillates in the form of Òdemoliciones y restauraciones sucesivas e incesantesÉÓ (103).
It is important to note that TorresÕs methodology of interrogating idols coincides with NietzscheÕs Òphilosophizing with a hammer,Ó which in The Twilight of the Idols (1888) means tapping idols to ascertain if they are empty or substantive. The symbolism of their respective tools utilized for this inquiry is likewise indicative of their respective attitudes. For example, NietzscheÕs hammer represents a demolishing, destructive tool, yet Torres insists that Òel emblema del esp’ritu de rectificacion es un cincel, no una piqueta; su mensaje es de perfeccionamiento, no de aniquilaci—nÓ (275). In this way, Torres situates his program between two philosophical extremes, between, on the one hand, the destructive nihilists whose deterministic views surrounding, for example, the superiority of certain races and, on the other, those who cling to inflexible dogmas because they are unwilling to accept the inevitable modifications of existence. This middle ground rejects the radicalism of the former and seeks to reform the Òmental stagnationÓ of the latter by emphasizing evolution and independence.  Above all, TorresÕs program seeks to replace the preconceived and predetermined nature of Òlas convicciones tradicionales e inquebrantablesÓ with Òlas convicciones racionales y perfectiblesÓ (278).
TorresÕs advocacy for an intellectual freedom free from certainty does not coincide with a Nietzschean-like individualism. In contrast, Torres sees individual development only within the larger social framework. Following English sociologist Benjamin Kidd, Torres asserts that Òde la integraci—n de las conciencias individuales surge una conciencia colectiva, diferente de cada una de las que la forman y superior a la suma de todas ellasÉÓ (115). In the same way, Torres denies the mutual exclusivity of individual freedom and national solidarity, an idea that was outlined by French politician Henri BŽrenger in La conscience nationale (1898). (7) National cohesion, much like the modern rhetoric surrounding bipartisanship, implies transcending party loyalties for the greater good.  According to Torres, the prevalence of a herd mentality accounts for the diminished propensity of the freedom to interrogate and criticize political parties (127). Torres blames the uncritical acceptance of and devotion to a political party for the facility with which violence erupts in and frustrates Latin American democracies.
The ideas of inherent change lead Torres to engage in a suggestive negotiation when he deconstructs the respective roles of an intellectual aristocracy and the masses in the post-war Colombian national project. A central component of Ariel and arielismo, informed by BŽrenger and Gustave Le Bon, portrays the masses as unable to transcend their instinctive impulses. (8) Torres echoes this notion by dehumanizing the masses: Òel impulso de las multitudes representa cuanto hay de m‡s inconsciente e irrazonado en las acciones humanasquerer allegar un ‡tomo de raz—n a esas impulsiones instintivas ser’a tanto como pretender discutir con el terremoto o convencer al cicl—nÉÓ (Torres 132). Such a correlation reveals an elitist attitude that, in addition to denying legitimate agency to the masses, fears their unbridled impulses.
Like Rod—, Torres attributes to the masses a primitive instinct that precludes them from defining a moral compass as well as from generating ÔreasonableÕ courses of action within a national framework. The crowdÕs inconsciencia accounts for its pliability with respect to base emotions such as violence (132). Although ÒspiritÓ became a key word after Ariel, its definition was flexible. Torres cites Gustave Le BonÕs widely influential Psychologie des Foules (1895) to call into question the very existence of the crowdÕs spirit and conscience. If these do exist, Torres maintains, Òson un esp’ritu informe y una conciencia obscura y primitiva de donde la verdad y la justicia no emanan sino raza vez, en r‡fagas moment‡neas, en inspiraciones tornadizas y ef’merasÉÓ (133). Torres proposes a thinking elite to fill the critical void left by what he considers the massÕs innate tendency to follow the herd, which has been responsible for the widespread violence and dictatorships that have occurred throughout Latin American republics.  Throughout history, Torres argues, steering civilization toward higher ideals has been the obligation of Òlas mentes superiores que se han atrevido a tener raz—n contra los dem‡sÉÓ (135). (9) Such outstanding individuals are capable of envisioning the future and therefore their primary task is, and always has been, to pass Òla antorcha de la verdad sobre el espeso manto de tinieblas en que las multitudes se envuelven obstinadamente para negar la luzÓ (134). (10)
For Torres, a successful democracy means having a directive intelligentsia that can divulge validated ideas and actions via a Òcultivated criterion.Ó Although Torres recognizes the divisive implications of his ideas surrounding equality and legitimate hierarchies, he states that they are less extreme because they do not coincide with the scientific aristocratism of the nineteenth century that gave way to racialized diagnostics. Significantly, although Torres insists on the validity of intellectual hierarchies, he also disdains what he calls herolatr’a (hero worship), a concept borrowed from Scottish writer Thomas Carlyle. In On Heroes and Hero Worship (1840), Carlyle examines six varieties (11) of Ògreat menÓ throughout history, such as Mohammed, Dante, Shakespeare, Luther, Rousseau, Cromwell, and Napoleon, and, as the following passage illustrates, casts them as almost supernatural beings:

[The hero] is the living light-fountain, which it is good and pleasant to be near.  The light which enlightens, which has enlightened the darkness of the world; and this is not as a kindled lamp only, but rather as a natural luminary shining by the gift of Heaven; a flowing light-fountain, as I say, of native original insight, of manhood and heroic nobleness;¾in whose radiance all souls feel that it is well with them. (Carlyle 4)

Although his endorsement of the directive roles of a sanctioned intelligentsia seemingly participates in CarlyleÕs hyperbolic hero fascination, Torres attempts to stabilize this by validating the progressive roles that anonymous individuals and groups have played throughout history. (12)  Imagining a nation frequently involves mythologizing one figure (for example, Bol’var, Napoleon) and projects onto this person all the accomplishments of a collective effort.  According to Torres, this mythologizing tendency is a selective history that privileges hero worship without acknowledging the participation of those people and groups whom national histories and popular narratives overlook. Torres, then, inverts his earlier assertions regarding the incapacity of the masses to participate in national pursuits and insists that Òson las masas el granito esencial de la grandeza de las nacionesÓ (188). 
According to Czech political theorist Miroslav Hroch, collective memory and equality are two key features of nation-building processes (79). While for Hroch these two facets are not mutually exclusive, Torres interrogates popular myths that inform cultural memory in order to grant agency to and incorporate a larger percentage of the population in the reconstruction of Colombia.  Of course, the incongruity between TorresÕs initial denigration of the masses and his subsequent calls to reject Òtoda especie de directores de conciencia o de directores de pensamientoÓ (188), manifests the oscillative and paradoxical nature of assessing and assigning roles in a post-war national reconstruction. (13)
Although in ÒRumbos nuevosÓ Rod— applauds TorresÕs emphasis on equilibrium, Rod— criticizes the Colombian for his insufficient recognition of the importance of legitimate hierarchies.  Rod— observes a discrepancy between, on the one hand, TorresÕs advocacy for a directive class and, on the other, his protestations against hero worship. According to Rod—, Òal impugnar la superstici—n aristocr‡tica, [Torres] no reconoce todo su valor de oportunidad a la obra de instituir, en el alma de estos pueblos, el sentimiento de la autoridad vinculada a las leg’timas aristocracias del esp’ritu, para la orientaci—n y el gobierno de la conciencia colectivaÓ (ÒRumbosÓ 48). For Rod—, Torres went too far in attempting to encourage collective participation in imagining the Colombian nation.  Despite TorresÕs clear repudiation of the masses in certain moments of the essay, Rod— felt it necessary to insist once more, as he had done consistently since Ariel, on the absolute legitimacy of a directive intellectual class.
In other words, Rod— recognizes the importance of equilibrium with respect to positivism and spiritualism, but he is firm in his dichotomous, elitist division between a privileged minority who charts the course for society and the crowd, who should follow their lead because it is unable to generate any substantive sociopolitical progress on its own. While Rod— commends TorresÕs balanced approach in êdola fori, the Uruguayan feels that the Colombian takes his emphasis on balance too far. Specifically, Rod— criticizes Torres for calling what the Uruguayan considers to be legitimate intellectual authorities an Òaristocratic superstitionÓ (Torres 165). However, it is important to remember that unlike Rod—, Torres writes his essay in the midst of a national crisis and therefore does not have the luxury of speaking metaphorically or restricting who can and cannot participate in the reconstruction of post-war Colombia. In other words, in the years following the divisive military and political struggles, in the years following los Mil D’as Torres sought to avoid the exclusionary policies that spawned the divisive military and political struggles that ravaged Colombia.
Although êdola fori is one of the most widely-read mediums for sharing universal intellectual currents in Latin America in the decade of 1910, literary histories rarely offer more than a quick aside about it. Moreover, critics who have commented TorresÕs essay view it in an ambivalent manner. For example, as already mentioned above, while Medardo Vitier praises TorresÕs ability to incorporate a wide variety of scientific, philosophical, and political ideas into êdola fori, he laments that these derive from predominantly European sources (165).  Due to TorresÕs ÒapplicationÓ of European ideas to Latin American realities, Vitier classifies the ColombianÕs Americanism as ÒindirectÓ (157). (14) In addition, from the perspective of two important U.S. commentators of the Latin American essay, Earle and Mead, Torres is anything but moderate and calm like êdola fori. Despite these critical assertions that date from the 1940s and 1970s, more recent critics such as Sierra Mej’a tend to read êdola fori as a very balanced and serene essay written to quell an era dominated by violence and division. TorresÕs emphasis on peace and cooperation will undoubtedly be attractive to readers who live in bitterly hyper-partisan political environments, or near rapidly-shifting borders, today. Moreover, Torres stipulates that a successful democracy depends on reason, tolerance, and inclusion. In his estimation the revolts and civil wars in Colombia were fueled by the divisive political ideas and ideologies of a few politicians. The problem was not primarily a power-hungry caudillo, although Torres was critical of this strong man too, but rather uncritical ideas used by interested parties. Although Torres underscored the importance of rational ideas, he did so by focusing on serenity, relativity, and sociability (Jaramillo Uribe 443).
For over a century, Torres has been essentially dismissed by critics of Latin American literature. When scholars do mention him, they generally label him an ÔarielistaÕ. His connection with arielismo is evident from Rod—Õs prologue, which suggests that both essayists shared a similar pedagogical mission. However, each essayist wrote from very different places and in vastly distinct circumstances: Rod— writes from a small, wealthy country on the verge of an expansive social democracy, while Torres finds himself in the economic and cultural aftermaths of a civil war. In other words, Rod—Õs spiritualism was too vague and simplistic for the post-war necessities of Colombia, which required utilitarian and practical pursuits (Sierra Mej’a Carlos Arturo Torres 23-25). Rod— overlooks the plethora of geopolitical realities that inform cultural production in Colombia in the post-war period. Civil wars, a contentious political system, and the succession of Panama with the intervention of the United States, necessitate a different reading of TorresÕs essay outside a strictly arielista paradigm.
As I have pointed out, TorresÕs principle disjunction with Rod—Õs arielismo lies in the notion of legitimate hierarchies. Initially, Torres validates Rod—Õs elitist vision in no uncertain terms.  Subsequently, however, he argues against the exclusivity of Ariel by insisting that all members of a nation, not just the select intellectual minority, deserve to participate in determining the direction of their countries. Rod—Õs restrictive view of democracy is incongruous with the geopolitical realities in post-war Colombia that necessitated a more inclusive vision for democratic participation. In other words, Torres realized from first hand experience that exclusivity and hyper-partisanship are synonymous and counterproductive for democratic projects. Therefore, Rod—Õs continentalist discourse that advocates an elitist, spiritualist transcendence of material realities and utilitarian endeavors contrasts sharply with TorresÕs role as a man of state trying to navigate and reconcile the complexities of a highly polarized political situation in Colombia.

Notes

(1). His works include Poemas simb—licos (1897), La abad’a de Westminster otros poemas (1902), Estudios ingleses and Estudios varios (1906).

(2). Bacon identifies four kinds of idols: idols of the Tribe, idols of the Cave, idols of the Marketplace and idols of the Theater (Bacon 20).

(3). ÒTorres no posee ni la tolerancia ni la elasticidad espiritual necesarias para comprender a los que defienden opiniones opuestas a las suyas.  Est‡ seguro de la verdad de sus aseveraciones y suele recibir la contradicci—n con el porte de ap—stol mal comprendidoÓ (Earle and Mead 57).

(4). The second edition of the essay (1916) is entitled Los ’dolos del foro.

(5). Vitier maintains that Torres offers an insufficient explanation of the theory of idols, which he believes accounts for the essayÕs inaccessibility for most Latin American readers (158).

(6). Colombian writer Gabriel Garc’a M‡rquez fictionalizes how these catastrophic events affected a small, isolated village called Macondo in his bestseller novel, Cien a–os de soledad (1967).

(7). BŽrengerÕs ideas also influenced Rod—, who mentions BŽrengerÕs L'aristocratie intellectuelle (1895) in Ariel (Cf. Rod— Ariel 191).

(8). For Rod—, there are two types of instinct; a dangerous instinct that manifests itself in the imitative tendencies of the masses and an ideal instinct that permits a select minority of the Òlegitimate human superioritiesÓ (Ariel 26) to transcend mediocre influences.

(9). For example, Carlyle, Nietzsche, Emerson, and William James all claimed that only exceptional men create history (Torres 165).

(10). Note how this description mirrors CarlyleÕs hero worship.

(11). The six kinds of heroes are: divine, prophet, poet, priest, man of letters, and king.

(12). British writer Carne Ross analyzes a recent resurgence of this idea in the Occupy Wall Street movement in the United States in his The Leaderless Revolution: How Ordinary People Will Take Charge and Change Politics in the 21st Century.

(13). Vitier opines that this negotiation is unsatisfactory because he believes that the references Torres provides in hopes of subverting CarlyleÕs hero worship actually reinforce it (168).

(14). It is curious, however, that Vitier does not apply the same standard to Rod—Õs Ariel, an essay that engages with an enormous quantity of European ideas, but cites very few Latin American sources.

Works Cited

Altamirano, Carlos. Historia de los intelectuales en AmŽrica Latina: Los avatares de la Òciudad letradaÓ en el siglo XX.  Buenos Aires: Katz Editores, 2008.

Bacon, Francis. Novum Organum.  New York: American Home Library Company, 1902.

Carlyle, Thomas. Heroes and Hero Worship. London: Chapman and Hall, 1869.

DevŽs ValdŽs, Eduardo. ÒEl pensamiento latinoamericano a comienzos del siglo XX: La reivindicaci—n de la identidad.Ó CUYO: Anuario de Filosof’a Argentina y Americana 14 (1997): 11-75.

Earle, Peter and Robert Mead.  Historia del ensayo hispanoamericano.  MŽxico: Ediciones de Andrea, 1973.

Fischer, Thomas. ÒDesarrollo hacia afuera y ÒrevolucionesÓ en Colombia, 1850-1910.Ó In Memoria de un pa’s en guerra: los Mil D’as: 1899-1902. Eds. Gonzalo S‡nchez and Mario Aguilera.  Bogot‡: Editorial Planeta Colombiana, S.A., 2001: 33-58.

Guy, Alain. ÒLe bergsonisme en AmŽrique latine.Ó Caravelle 1 (1963): 121-139.

Hroch, Miroslav. ÒFrom National Movement to the Fully-Formed Nation: The Nation-Building Process in Europe.Ó In Mapping the Nation. Ed. Gopal Balakrishnan.  New York: Verso, 1999: 78-97.

Jaramillo Uribe, Jaime.  El pensamiento colombiano en el siglo XIX.  Bogot‡: Editorial Temis, 1964.

Nietzsche, Friedrich.  The Anti-Christ, Ecce Homo, Twilight of the Idols, and Other Writings. Eds. Aaron Ridley and Judith Norman. Tran. Judith Norman.  Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010.

Oviedo, JosŽ Miguel.  Breve historia del ensayo hispanoamericano. Madrid: Alianza Editorial, 1990.

Posada Carb—, Eduardo.  ÒLas guerras civiles del siglo XIX en la AmŽrica Hisp‡nica.Ó  In Memoria de un pa’s en guerra: los Mil D’as: 1899-1902. Eds. Gonzalo S‡nchez and Mario Aguilera.  Bogot‡: Editorial Planeta Colombiana, S.A., 2001: 59-73.

Rod—, JosŽ Enrique. Ariel. Madrid: Ediciones C‡tedra, 2000.

-----.  ÒRumbos nuevos.Ó El mirador de Pr—spero. Valencia: Editorial Cervantes, 1919: 31-61.

Salazar C‡ceres, Carlos Gabriel.  Carlos Arturo Torres Pe–a: Vida, Žpoca, pensamiento. Boyac‡, Colombia: Editorial Talleres Gr‡ficos Ltda., 1997.

S‡nchez, Gonzalo and Mario Aguilera. ÒIntroducci—n.Ó  In Memoria de un pa’s en guerra: los Mil D’as: 1899-1902. Eds. Gonzalo S‡nchez and Mario Aguilera.  Bogot‡: Editorial Planeta Colombiana, S.A., 2001: 19-30.

Sierra Mej’a, RubŽn. Carlos Arturo Torres.  Bogot‡: Editorial Nomos, 1989.

-----.  ÒEl intelectual contra la guerra.Ó In Memoria de un pa’s en guerra: los Mil D’as: 1899-1902. Eds. Gonzalo S‡nchez and Mario Aguilera.  Bogot‡: Editorial Planeta Colombiana, S.A., 2001: 211-224.

Torres, Carlos Arturo. Los ’dolos del foro: ensayo sobre las supersticiones pol’ticas. Madrid: Editorial AmŽrica, 1916.

Vitier, Medardo. Del ensayo americano. MŽxico: Fondo de Cultura Econ—mica, 1945.